96 Comments
author

Consider peer review as a repugnant conclusion. A paper gets a bunch of comments from reviewers. Responding to each particular comment could make the paper better. But if you respond to every comment you’ll likely make the paper worse.

Expand full comment
May 1Liked by Misha Valdman

I think peer review is a a much better example than the others. It gets much closer to showing a contradiction between marginal improvements and overall optimization, which I doubt exists whatsoever in reality when it comes to burgers, walls, or lakes.

There's still might theoretically be an optimal version of each paper with optimal choices about which advice to take, but since there's a whole library of babel of potential things we could write and no perfect measurable standard by which to judge them all, or to determine which subjects are even worth writing about, I think it's a far trickier and more interesting problem.

With that said, I personally think it was an optimal choice to pay attention to comments asking for better examples, though obviously I'm biased since those included my own comments.

Expand full comment

"Written on the subway walls, you could be forgiven for overlooking that thought experiment’s profundity." I am not written on the subway walls, thankfully. (This sentence begins with a misplaced modifier.)

Expand full comment
author

I thought “were it written on the subway walls, you could be forgiven…” would be too stuffy. And I really wanted the allusion to the Sound of Silence :)

Expand full comment
Aug 23Liked by Misha Valdman

Sentences can always become less stuffy, but they also must become a little more ambiguous.

Expand full comment
May 6Liked by Misha Valdman

I thoroughly enjoyed your essay on the logic of the repugnant conclusion [RC], especially your witty and irreverent style of writing! I take the following to be your most general conclusion:

"But the repugnant conclusion can be deployed against any natural relation – is-bigger-than, is-mightier-than, is-clearer-than, is-more-useful-than – and not to goodness (or is-better-than) in particular. The open-question argument and the repugnant conclusion are manifestations of the same general problem – a failure of analysis – a gap that forms whenever one seeks clarity by breaking wholes into parts."

This resonates with another 'failure of analysis' known as (quantum) contextuality*: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Quantum_contextuality . Like the RC, though contextuality originated in one area of study (quantum physics), it has much broader applicability. The core insight of contextuality can be summarized as "local coherence but global incoherence".

A visual analogy is any of Escher's paradoxical structures, such as Ascending and Descending: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ascending_and_Descending . Any pair or triple of adjacent stairways is locally coherent, but all four stairways are globally incoherent. A logical example of contextuality is the the liar cycle: S1: S2 is true; S2: S3 is true; ... S(n-1): Sn is true; Sn: S1 is false. Any local subset of adjacent assertions is coherent, but the global set of assertions is incoherent.

It seems to me that the RC is another example of such contextuality: any local set of transitive comparisons is coherent, but the global set of comparisons is incoherent. As long as we remember to be pragmatically local in our observations and comparisons, we need not fear that the RC will "drag down us all". We only need remember that we can't always aggregate coherent local contexts into a holistic global context. (By the way, in the field of ethics, Pragmatists took this to heart with their localized concept of 'meliorism': focusing only on improving present conditions without aiming towards eventual perfection. I discuss such a 'directionless' melioristic approach here: https://erraticus.co/2022/10/27/what-can-pragmatists-hope-for-in-a-boundless-world/ .)

* Note that there are several bodies of work that go by the name "contextualism". I am speaking specifically about the body of work that originated in quantum physics, and which has been generalized using category theory by folks such as Samson Abramsky. For a good summary of Abramsky's work on contextuality, see 'At the Borders of Paradox' https://arxiv.org/pdf/2011.04899 .

Expand full comment
author

Thanks for those links! But I think the solution to the RC, if there is one, is to resist the lure of pragmatic locality and think big instead. Thinking locally reveals opportunities for gradual improvement, the steady accumulation of which tend to make things worse.

Expand full comment

You're welcome!

"resist the lure of pragmatic locality and think big instead"

Depending on how "big" "thinking big" is, it may be compatible with pragmatically local meliorism. Centuries-long projects (such as cathedral building or reducing carbon emissions) can nonetheless be local and incremental.

"the steady accumulation of [gradual improvements] tend to make things worse"

I agree. But major (non-gradual) improvements tend to make things worse as well. Just as there's always an upside, there's always a downside: improvements in some dimensions are balanced by worsenings in other dimensions.

Expand full comment
author

By “think big” I mean follow the categorical imperative. Don’t ask what would make things better on some particular occasion but on what would happen if your maxim became universal law. Repugnancy is a contradiction in the will. It’s what you get when you think in terms of pebbles rather than boulders. I’ll explain in a future post.

Expand full comment

"what would happen if your maxim became universal law"

From a contextualist perspective, maxims becoming universal laws would increase tragic suffering in some contexts and would decrease it in others. Universal laws, like parochial laws, are upayas (skillful means) that can be beneficial in some contexts and detrimental in others.

"I’ll explain in a future post."

I look forward to it!

Expand full comment
author

The issue is moreso that improvements in one dimension tend to cause worsenings in the very same dimension.

Rather than thinking big or thinking small, it would probably be best to avoid thinking at all.

Expand full comment
May 1Liked by Misha Valdman

Lessons we might learn from Parfit and Valdman:

Relations are not always transitive.

Quantities are not always commensurable.

Scaling is not always linear.

Results may be path-dependent.

If logic and intuition conflict, they may be trying to tell you something.

Expand full comment

This is beautifully written. Thank you!

Expand full comment

Brilliantly written and witty, put it better than I could have. I’m actually reading Parfit right now and this expresses brilliantly my difficulty with his writing style and obsession with distinctions. And yes as you say, all of that book is Parfit showing how a thing can become its opposite. But I loved how you showed how those two are related— how he takes distinction-making to such an extreme that it undermines itself.

I think it’s telling that analytic philosophy’s origin myth is Moore and Russell ‘disproving’ F. H. Bradley’s view on the unreality of distinctions

Expand full comment
author

Yeah, he didn't seem to realize that the paradoxes that undermine the pursuit of the good also undermine the pursuit of the clear.

BTW thanks for the Bradley tip. I didn't know much about him. But now I'm checking out his interactions with Russell and it's fascinating.

Expand full comment

Derek Parfit's exploration of population ethics is vividly likened to an ever-escalating paradox, where incremental choices lead to a repugnant conclusion. The narrative artfully illustrates how relentless pursuit of improvement can, paradoxically, lead to deterioration, a cautionary tale about the unintended consequences of rationality.

Expand full comment
May 14Liked by Misha Valdman

Very interesting article, came by way of the indominablte Soldo.

I am no philosopher, but the repugnant's dependence on trade-offs seems flawed, no? Why not have a bigger and deeper lake? A more tasty and less shitty burger?

It would seem day to day that there is no special law that dictates more at the cost of quality? In fact categorically, there are plenty of occasions where a person will either choose more and better quality (e.g. upgrading a house) or simply to opt out of more for less quality (McDonalds everyday).

I do think the analogy is apropos to what has happened largely in consumer technology (more convenience, but tradeoffs in things like privacy), electronics (more accessible to the masses, but at great cost to longevity, etc..) but i don't know if these were consciously made or rather just driven by techno-capitalism as opposed to clambering for goodness?

Happily now a subscriber!

Expand full comment
author

You're asking: isn't it possible to make things better along some dimension without making them worse along another dimension? The short answer is: I don't know. I suspect that it isn't possible, and that it only seems possible in some cases, like the ones you mention, because of ignorance (because we don't know or can't detect how we're making things worse). But it also doesn't matter, because the repugnant conclusion is like flypaper: maybe you can avoid it for a little while, but eventually you'll land on it and get stuck. It's just a matter of time.

Expand full comment
May 1Liked by Misha Valdman

As much as I enjoyed this article which, so far as I can tell, is about what Cory Doctorow called "the enshittification of everything," but I can't help but suspect the conclusion. Doctorow describes a process endemic to digital capitalism; you see it as fundemental to reason. It seems distinctly anti-ameliorist, but very familiar in our political economy, to demand that in order to get better, you must be prepared to swallow some shit, and I worry that your conclusion engrains such a viewpoint as fundamental, not social. Is it really too utopian to think that a shitless burger is somehow possible?

Expand full comment
author

It might be fundamental to anything that's trying to outrun its contradictions, which would include reason, capitalism, people, institutions, and maybe the universe itself. As for a shitless burger, I think it's possible.. It's even possible to run the repugnant conclusion in reverse, from Z to Y to X and all the way to A. But that's not the natural flow. It's swimming upstream. You can do it for a while but eventually the current gets you.

Expand full comment

This was very enjoyable to read, thanks for writing it, Misha.

Expand full comment

One of the most interesting things I've learned in the realm of philosophy. Thank you for writing this.

Also fun to read.

Expand full comment
May 1Liked by Misha Valdman

Applying the repugnant conclusion to ‘x-ness’ makes me that we are just incapable of imagining any concept where there aren’t diminishing marginal returns. We’re finite creatures reasoning about infinite increases. Doubling x is possible in mathematics, but in the physical world Zeno’s arrow hits its target. It’s impossible to imagine a burger doubling in deliciousness infinitely because at a certain point we don’t think we could tell the difference — we asymptotically approach the ‘most delicious’ burger. We can’t think imagine infinite doubling of happiness or clarity for the same reason. To a certain extent we can imagine someone is happier than another, but at a certain point we’d just say they’re both pretty happy.

Expand full comment
author

Zeno’s arrow hits its target empirically (i.e. in reality) but not a priori (i.e. in reason). The repugnant conclusion is a problem in reason. But reason, more and more, is impinging on reality. And reason tells you that B is better than A, C is better than B, etc.

Expand full comment

"Zeno’s arrow hits its target empirically (i.e. in reality) but not a priori (i.e. in reason)." Is that right, though?

That the sum of an infinite number of infinitely diminishing addenda can be a finite number is not (only) an empirical conclusion, but a feature of mathematics since Leibniz and Newton - I think there might be some a priori reasoning behind calculus...

Expand full comment
author

Check out the St. Petersburg paradox: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/paradox-stpetersburg/

The empirical world and the a priori aren’t always in sync.

Expand full comment

Thank you for the link (though it doesn't seem to me that you have really answered to my enquiry), where, on swift perusal, I find this other possible objection to your line of reasoning:

"mathematicians value money in proportion to its quantity, and men of good sense in proportion to the usage that they may make of it. That which renders the mathematical expectation infinite, is the prodigious sum that I am able to receive, if the side of Heads falls only very late, the 100th or 1000th toss. Now this sum, if I reason as a sensible man, is not more for me, does not make more pleasure for me, does not engage me more to accept the game, than if it would be only 10 or 20 million coins. (Cramér to N. Bernouilli, 21 May 1728)"

Maybe there is something different in moral decisions...

Expand full comment
author

Doesn’t that just confirm my view? He’s basically saying that calculations of expected value are one thing and common sense is another, which is just another way of saying that the empirical and the a priori can diverge.

Expand full comment
May 1Liked by Misha Valdman

Well, sounds like you are right. I guess i gots some readin' to do. Thanks for responding. I'm still thinking about how this reason generalizes. Great stuff. All the best.

Expand full comment
Apr 30Liked by Misha Valdman

I think I read the z version of this essay

Expand full comment
author

Law bomb lobbed!

Expand full comment
Apr 30Liked by Misha Valdman

The East Indies, genius

Expand full comment

"Humanity suffers from the crippling problem that it’s always possible to make things x-er (bigger, better, stronger, clearer)."

Rubbish. Real world problems usually depend on trade-offs which lead to an 'optimal' solution(s) which cannot be improved further. Intelligent people will wait until they reach a region of diminishing returns and stop bother with making things X-er.

Expand full comment
author

As with gravity and natural selection, there are countervailing forces. But you can’t outrun the repugnant conclusion forever. In the end it turns everything to dust — civilizations, theories, people — A to B to C and all the way to Z.

Expand full comment

Sorry Misha, but Tek Bunny is right and your burger example doesn’t work—for reasons that Economics sorted out in the 1860s, when it introduced the concept of the margin.

You can of course make a plain burger (burger A) more delicious by adding beetroot in burger B, and even more delicious by adding sauce in burger C. But you can’t in fact go on making burgers twice as delicious as their predecessors. Adding pepper may make burger D a little better, but not much. The marginal value of each addition at some point becomes less, and may even be negative.

On the other hand, the marginal values of the unpleasantness of the additional shit may rise from zero (when the shit is imperceptible) to very large when it becomes perceptible.

At that point, the marginal value for the burger as a whole becomes negative. Burger H is of less value than burger G, but burger G is definitely better than burger A. The burger example fails, and I suspect that the castle wall and lake examples do as well.

More generally, while I’m not familiar with the debate over Parfit, I suspect that one’s conclusions would depend on one’s views on Kantian claims that all reason is characterised by contradiction, or on post-modern claims that language is similarly afflicted, and/or on the paradoxes of Zeno and Russell. Parfit might be right, but the examples you give don’t adequately capture the problem.

Expand full comment
author

Whether you could in fact produce such a burger sequence is irrelevant. In principle, for any food, B could be tastier than A, C could be tastier than B, and so on. But A could be tastier than Z.

Expand full comment

> Whether you could in fact produce such a burger sequence is irrelevant.

If you want to leave the comfortable confines of abstract theory and its frictionless surfaces, and apply them in the less forgiving world of object level reality (as seems to be what is implied in the essay) it is certainly not irrelevant.

Again, this demonstrates the power stories have over the human mind.

Expand full comment
author

I'm not sure I follow completely, but I'd say that the "story" you're referring to just is the idea that the a priori world (of abstract theory and its frictionless surfaces, as you put it) and the empirical world are one and the same. And the repugnant conclusion, I believe, shows that they're different.

Expand full comment

The story (stories) I am referring to is the story that the mind tells one about any given proposition or point of contention, and the related story it tells about the accuracy of its prior stories.

Kinda like "How is babby formed?", except instead of babby, reality.

Expand full comment
author

Object level reality is abstract theory.

Expand full comment

This is an interesting belief, can you cite any academic material that supports it?

Expand full comment

Whether something like a soul continues to exist is an interesting and fun question to consider though, it can provide lots of opportunities to ask scientific ideologues if a perceived/asserted absence of evidence is proof of absence....and then watch them go into story telling mode, as is easily predicted.

LLM's may not be an exact repetition of what human are, but they sure do rhyme with them.

Expand full comment

If it was not actually the way you describe it, would you necessarily be able to detect it?

Or another way of putting it: how do you know(!) that it is the way it seems to you? Have you a methodology for identifying objective optimality? How could such a thing be fact checked, by using the same claimed-to-be-optimal-yielding methodology?

Expand full comment
author

The measure of optimality is intuition; the repugnant conclusion shows that our intuitions do not obey transitivity. Do with that what you will.

Expand full comment

> The measure of optimality is intuition

No, intuition is a (typically subconscious) *prediction* of optimality. Typically, actual optimality cannot be measured, and in our culture when facts are not available, we hallucinate ~"cultural/personal facts" into existence. There are all sorts of weird hallucinations like this within our culture.

Expand full comment

'Our intuitions are not transitive'?? Thanks for the simplistic profundity Yoda. Maybe look up Arrow's Theorem sometime.

Expand full comment

That is not correct! Optimality is always defined w/ reference to some higher order good. For the wall, the higher order good is mightiness (effectiveness at keeping people out). The supremely thin and tall wall is obviously not mighty, but there is a wall which is just the right height and thickness to be the mightiest wall, given constraints. Note that superiority of this wall to ones which are slightly taller and thinner or thicker and shorter does NOT violate transitivity - this bundle of width and height is transitively better than those alternatives.

As Misha points out, pretty much everything in the world is like this.

But Parfit is not myopic for thinking that goodness itself should be different. There can be no higher order good than goodness itself, so a simple “more is more” philosophy should suffice for finding the transitively optimal bundle. The repugnance of his conclusion, and the preference intransitivity it implies, shows that utility cannot be such an ultimate good.

Utilitarianism is an important moral philosophy, so this problematisation is a worthy subject of discussion. But it doesn’t follow that our actual moral preferences are intransitive and that moral philosophical inquiry is therefore doomed to fail, as Misha seems to suggest.

In particular, the possibility remains that there is some other higher order good that you can maximise in a transitive way by optimally trading off average utility against total utility.

What this higher order good might be and how to maximise it is a tough question, but I think it’s clearly a normal and sensible question that we can come up with various plausible answers to. Indeed, Parfit seemed satisfied that he had come up with an answer in the final years of his life!

So the RC is a useful problem for moral philosophers to discuss, but it is not so problematic that it portends doom for all efforts to solve problems that look even vaguely like it. In other words, Parfit was fully justified in spending a lot of time working on it!

Likewise, Parfit seems to have been perfectly capable of arriving at good conclusions to the important and difficult question of how much philosophical clarity it was worth his while to provide. He was indeed a perfectionist and probably should have worried less about loose ends, but he’s clearly been pretty well vindicated by history! RAP and OWM are excellent, well-regarded books, and I’m glad that Parfit spent a lot of time working on them before ultimately calling it a day and sending them off to the presses, warts and all.

Parfit was a good, sensible, and successful person who was correctly willing to eat a certain amount of shit in order to make progress. How many of us can say the same for ourselves?

Expand full comment
author

>there is a wall which is just the right height and thickness to be the mightiest wall

Ok, what height and thickness is that?

Expand full comment

Well like obviously it depends on the circumstance. The point is that for utilitarians, the best amount of utility should not depend on anything - more should always be better. But in the RC, that seems not to be the case. That is a problem for utilitarians, but it is a problem that can be solved, for example by conceding that goodness depends on more than just total utility. If this is the case, then there are conditions under which some outcome between A and Z is optimal.

For example, you could think that if adding an extra person would bring average utility below a certain critical level, then you should not add an extra person, even if doing so would increase total utility. This is like saying that there's no use in adding bricks to a wall if the wall is still too thin to serve its purpose.

In philosophy and in life, Parfit seemed to accept a version of this. He talked about how some profound experience were lexically better than less profound types, so that no amount of lizards basking in the sun could make up for the loss of one human moment of true love, for example. In his writing, he recognised that his two books were better off published than perfect.

It's true that he went further along the path from A to Z than most in evaluating such trade-offs, but given his monumental impact, I don't think we can say that this approach ultimately left him eating shit.

Expand full comment

It's the other way round. Where is any evidence for the nonsense of the statement I quoted. The norm of every system we study, whether physical or biological or social, is to have complex non linear dynamics. Making things incrementally and continuously X-er is something we have no example of.

Expand full comment
May 3·edited May 3

> It's the other way round. Where is any evidence for the nonsense of the statement I quoted.

You have it backwards. What you are trying to do is "shift the burden of proof".

Here is a question, I am interested in whether you have the ability to coerce your mind into attempting an answer to it: "If it was not actually the way you describe it, would you necessarily be able to detect it?"

Now, having reposed the very same question, I can now observe if you behave any differently than the last time I asked....and for extra fun: I am explicitly revealing the experiment I am running!

> The norm of every system we study, whether physical or biological or social, is to have complex non linear dynamics. Making things incrementally and continuously X-er is something we have no example of.

Do you genuinely believe that you possess genuine omniscient knowledge (on this claim, and your prior ones)?

Expand full comment